How the world works and our mind

How the world works and our mind

AN EFFORT TO COMPREHEND POSSIBLE WAYS TO UNDERSTAND THE WORKING OF THE REAL-WORLD FUNCTION

?A three-dimensional universe

?If we have to prove?the being of a 4 spatial dimension universe. But it is difficult to prove conventions of elucidations like the Copenhagen interpretation, or?parallel-world interpretation. There are some suggestions also, on how to prove it, like, Lisa Randall endeavors to prove it with high energy?collider.

?The universe is four-dimensional, which we believe is a?three-dimensional world. In this universe, we?have a pinpoint in space with 4?numbers (x, y, z,l) or five numbers if?we include the time which signifies the event only not the location. An event is occurring in?a place and a period measured from a?distinct starting point, like the birth of Christ. It is pointless to relate time to location. Therefore, hereafter we refer?only to spatial dimensions which are called 4D not 5D. The question arises the reason for not perceiving the world in four?spatial dimensions, as we have?not yet developed ability in the course of evolution. To clarify that a 4D universe can be?real, let us consider a fish with two-dimensional vision. But a fish in a?pond with two-dimensional vision can move in the third dimension.?It can, but it probably will think it is visiting a new?place in its two-dimensional world. Similarly, maybe we?can move in all four directions, but we?think when moving to a new position we are visiting a new?3D place because of our limited three-dimensional vision.?A smart fish can deduce the third dimension's?existence by measuring the different temperatures at different heights or finding other third dimension phenomena. Likewise, we can deduce the fourth dimension by measuring phenomena that can be explained only by a?four-dimensional universe, like the imbroglio phenomenon. ?

The followings are some complications in physics that a four-dimensional universe can?solve:

?Entanglement is at the heart of quantum physics and future quantum technologies. Like other aspects of quantum science, the phenomenon of entanglement reveals itself at very tiny, subatomic scales. When two particles, such as a pair of photons or electrons, become entangled, they remain connected even when separated by vast distances. In the same way that ballet or tango emerges from individual dancers, entanglement arises from the connection between particles. It is what scientists call an emergent property.

Entanglement:

?It is very intricate to understand and explain the entanglement phenomenon by assuming that the two electrons (or photons) are still adjacent in the 4th dimension even if we separate them in the other 3rd dimension. Therefore, they can exchange information instantly, notwithstanding their?3D separation. The much smaller force of?gravity than all three primary forces can be explained by assuming that the gravitational force resides in the?4th dimension.?The unifying?of Maxwell's electromagnetic equations and Einstein's relativistic equations, (the Kaluza-Klein theory). Consideration of the quantum theory avoids?the problematic Copenhagen interpretation. ?

The 4th-dimensional universe supposition can explain many physics conundrums and is a simple theory therefore is preferred by the rule?of the Occam razor. But it is difficult to visualize a?way to move in the 4th ?dimension. It is easier in the?theory in the universe is?visions as a four-dimensional world where we are on a 3D brain residing in a 4D?substance. If we can move toward the 4th dimension and?then move along the 3D to another place, and then?go back – we will manage teleportation to the new 3D location.?A fish with 2D?vision cannot comprehend a?3D universe, it will probably think that it is moving toward a new 2D location even if it is moving in the 3rd dimension direction. How will these fish see another fish if we?take it out of the water and put it?down in another location? Probably it will think that teleportation happened. ?In one instance the fish was near and in the other instance, it emerges there. Perhaps this is why fishes jump?in the air -?to appear from nowhere and confuse the prayer. We have only 3D vision. We cannot imagine a?movement in the fourth dimension and will assume, we are moving toward a new 3D location even if?we are moving in the?fourth-dimension direction, but if?we can move deep into the 4th dimension and disappear from people's eyes, and?then re-appear in another location – that is?teleportation. Teleportation is the hypothetical transfer of matter or energy from one point to another without traversing the physical space between them. It is a common subject in science fiction transport.

?The problem in explaining a 4D universe

??A fish can move in the third dimension by changing its fin’s angle. It appears that we are not enabled to move?in this direction which indicates that perhaps there is no fourth dimension, as it should be an?evolutionary advantage to whoever could?move in the fourth dimension. But still, perhaps the mutation to have such ability was not yet found or was not very useful. But that does not prove there is?no 4th ??dimension.

??A fish will notice that an object changes its form when it moves and turns (because it is 3dimensional and not symmetric). Such a phenomenon is not observed when we?look at other objects, indicating that the objects we see are not four-dimensional. But perhaps all 3D objects are not moving in the fourth dimension?or they all are entangled. If an entangled electron is indeed adjacent to the other electron in the fourth dimension?and decoherence makes them move apart, it really means that when we are in?a coherence system there is no movement?in the fourth dimension and we cannot see a difference when an object is moving. Of Coarse there can be an explanation we do not know yet.

If not all objects in the universe are?four-dimensional objects, then we have to embrace the?more complicated Brane theory that place the three-dimension objects on 3-dimension?branes residing in the four-dimension substance. Gravitons can be in?the bulk (or another brane) according to this theory.?Anyway, the hierarchy problem, and the entanglement phenomenon, are best explained as four-dimensional objects.

?A method to prove the?presence of the fourth-dimension

?The fact that assuming the 4D universe enlightens many riddles in physics and unifies theories is?in itself proof of the existence of?the 4D universe.?According to Einstein, the phenomenon of gravity is?due to the distortion of the geometry of three-dimensional spatial space in the vicinity of large mass - creating a socket into which the?less massive bodies roll. The three-dimensional space can be distorted to the fourth spatial dimension. If the distortion is?relatively small, like what happens near the?sun, it allows for?attracting smaller masses (like planets) towards the sun. Scientists measured light deviation from a distant star passing near the sun,?proving Einstein's explanation of gravity's nature. The study of black holes can produce another proof. Physicists propose to prove the existence?of a fourth dimension by finding?typical fourth-dimension particles in the new?powerful collider. Presenting the 4th dimension gives us another degree?of freedom, like that of mufti-universes in Everett's interpretation. This can interpret quantum mechanics in a more graceful way. There may be time dimensions as well. It can?explain many unexplained mysteries.

Road-map for future examination

?A roadmap is a strategic planning technique that places a project’s goals and major deliverables (tasks, milestones) on a timeline, all grouped in a single visual representation or graphic. Therefore, to scrutinize our?world again with the assumption that we live in an extra-dimensional?world and not in the three spatial dimensions we assumed used to think we are in.

?Primary elementary assumptions

?To explain the enigmatic phenomena of quantum mechanics, we first have to explore the?essence of some of the basic features of physics. We can define?them only by what we measure, and we must?take into account the interactions done in the measuring process. We?can introduce hypotheses regarding their essence, but experimental physicists have to verify them. We also have to?be aware that sometimes our measurements change the measuring object, and sometimes they measure something else. Like, we can measure wave energy, and?think we measure mass.

?SOME HYPOTHESIS ?

?Though spin has nothing to do with a?spinning particle, we do not know what spin is. If an electron spins around the core of?an atom, it will induce a magnetic field,?lose energy, and fall toward the core.?The fact that?it does not fall?indicates that it resides as a standing wave in the distance proportional to its energy. Still, the standing wave oscillates, creating a small magnetic field?that can be only?in two states because there is only an up or?downstate in the standing wave. That is what we measure in the Garlich experiment. Maybe spin is an attribute of the electron that resides in?a 4-dimensional universe (or more) and affects the lower dimensions.

We generally specify a wave as a ripple of something. It can?be a wave of gravity, light, mass, or any other object.?A wave can come in two forms: Matter (or other stuff) is transferred from one place to the other -?in this case, the material can pass through space (like light). There is a disturbance - change in?amplitude, while the carrying matter stays. In this case, there must be a material base (ether).

?We are aware the resistance to acceleration measures that mass, but we also know that mass can become energy according to the Einstein formula E = mc2.?So, one wonders if a measurement of a?wave (which is energy) cannot, under certain conditions, be seen as mass. Einstein found?that light wave comes as packets. Physicists call these packets – particles, a misleading name.?One can think that light?waves are made of matter and disregard their wave nature. Two slit experiments prove them wrong. The two-slit experiment is thought to demonstrate the famous "collapse" of the wave function or "reduction" of the wave packet, which show an inherent probabilistic element in quantum mechanics that is irreducibly ontological and nothing like the epistemological indeterminacy (human ignorance) in classical statistical physics. The double-slit experiment is a classic experiment that definitely has to go over it, and is frequently referred to when describing quantum phenomena, so we describe wave packets of light (or any other waveform) act like waves and still can impact when colliding with other particles. Particles and waves are not different. Separating two entangled electrons in the 3-dimensional space does not separate them in the higher dimensions. Changing the spin direction of one electron will instantly change the spin direction of the adjutant entangled electron. This idea can be explained by the visualization?of two people standing far apart on a flat surface. Both will measure the same atmospheric pressure because they are still in the same place (height) regarding the?third dimension, no matter how far we separate on the?plain.

?Their extra?dimension is a small curled hidden dimension. Small extra dimension does not explain entanglement experiments showing this phenomenon to exist over vast distances (currently 400 KM), which drove some well-known physic scientists to accept large extra dimension (LED). Scientists fail to recognize large spatial dimensions because we humans cannot see it. The fact that we cannot experience the fourth dimension or many?other natural phenomena is due to the way of developments in the evolutionary process to develop only traits that help us survive.?A thesis should?explain all other strange phenomena we encounter in quantum experiments, the strange behavior of the electron's spin when measured by the Stern-Gerlach machine, and the two-slit experiment.

?

THE MIND/BRAIN IDENTITY THEORY

The identity theory of mind holds that states and processes of the mind are identical to states and processes of the brain. Strictly speaking, it need not hold that the mind is identical to the brain. Idiomatically we do use ‘She has a good mind’ and ‘She has a good brain’ interchangeably but we would not state its weigh 6 ounces. So our way of recognizing mind and brain as being a matter of identifying processes and perhaps states of the mind and brain. Consider an experience of pain, or of seeing something, or having a mental image. The identity theory of mind is to the effect that these experiences just?are?brain processes, not merely?correlated with?brain processes.

Some philosophers hold that though experiences are brain processes they nevertheless have fundamentally non-physical, psychical, properties, sometimes called ‘qualia’. Nevertheless, we can state the identity theory as denying the existence of such irreducible non-physical properties. Some identity theorists give a behavioristic analysis of mental?states, such as beliefs and desires, but others, sometimes called ‘central state materialists’, say that mental states are actual brain states. Identity theorists often describe themselves as ‘materialists’ but ‘physicalists’ may be a better word. That is, one might be a materialist about mind but nevertheless hold that there are entities referred to in physics that are not happily described as ‘material’.

Accepting the identity theory (in its various forms) as a species of physicalism, this is an ontological, not a translational physicalism. Ontology is the philosophical study of being, as well as related concepts such as existence, becoming, and reality. It would be absurd to try to translate sentences containing the word ‘brain’ or the word ‘sensation’ into sentences about electrons, protons and so on. Nor can we so translate sentences containing the word ‘tree’. After all ‘tree’ is largely learned extensively, and is not even part of botanical classification. If we were small enough a dandelion might count as a tree. Nevertheless, a physicalist could say that trees are complicated physical mechanisms. The physicalist will deny strong emergence in the sense of some philosophers. They latter pronounced that as far as was known at that time the properties of common salt cannot be deduced from the properties of sodium in isolation and of chlorine in isolation. (He put it too epistemologically: chaos theory shows that even in a deterministic theory physical consequence can outrun predictability.) Of course, the physicalist will not deny the harmless sense of "emergence" in which an apparatus is not just a jumble of its part.

The identity theory as I understand it here goes back to U.T. Place and Herbert Feigl in the 1950s. Historically philosophers and scientists, for example, Leucippus, Hobbes, La Mettrie, and d'Holbach, as well as Karl Vogt who, following Pierre-Jean-Georges Cabanis, made the absurd remark that the brain secretes thought as the liver secretes bile, have embraced materialism. However, here we shall date interest in the identity theory from the pioneering papers ‘Is Consciousness a Brain Process?’ by U.T. Place and H. Feigl ‘The "Mental" and the "Physical"’. Nevertheless, mention should be made of propositions by Rudolf Carnap, H. Reichenbach, and M. Schlick. Reichenbach said that mental events can be identified by the corresponding stimuli and responses much as the (possibly unknown) internal state of a photo-electric cell can be identified by the stimulus (light falling on it) and response (electric current flowing) from it. In both cases, the internal states can be physical states. However, Carnap did regard the identity as a linguistic recommendation rather than as asserting a question of fact. ?The psychologist E.G. Boring may well have been the first to use the term ‘identity theory.

Place's very original and pioneering paper was written after discussions at the University of Adelaide with J.J.C. Smart and C.B. Martin. For recollections of Martin's contributions to the discussion see Place. ‘Low Claim Assertions’ in Heil Smart at the time argued for a behaviorist position in which mental events were elucidated purely in terms of hypothetical propositions about behavior, as well as first person reports of experiences which Gilbert Ryle regarded as ‘avowals’. Avowals were thought of as mere pieces of behavior, as if saying that one had a pain was just doing a sophisticated sort of wince. Smart saw Ryle's theory as friendly to physicalism though that was not part of Ryle's motivation. Smart hoped that the hypotheticals would ultimately be explained by neuroscience and cybernetics. Being unable to refute Place, and recognizing the no-satisfactoriness of Ryle's treatment of inner experience, to some extent recognized by Ryle himself. Smart soon became converted to Place's view. ?In this he was also encouraged and influenced by Feigl's ‘"The Mental" and the "Physical" ’ ?Feigl's wide ranging contribution covered many problems, including those connected with intentionality, and he introduced the useful term ‘nomological danglers’ for the dualists' supposed mental-physical correlations. They would dangle from the nomological net of physical science and should strike one as an implausible excrescence on the fair face of science.

The Nature of the Identity Theory

The Pace spoke of the constitution rather than of identity. One of his examples is ‘This table is an old packing case’. Another is ‘that lightning is an electric discharge. Indeed, this latter was foreshadowed by Place in his earlier paper ‘The Concept of Heed’ in which he took issue with Ryle's behaviorism as it applied to concepts of consciousness, sensation, and imagery as Place remarked. The logical objections which might be raised to the statement ‘consciousness is a process in the brain’ are no greater than the logical objections which might be raised to the statement ‘lightning is a motion of electric charges.

It should be noticed that Place was using the word ‘logical’ in the way that it was used at Oxford at the time, not in the way that it is normally used now. One objection was that ‘sensation’ does not mean the same as ‘brain process’. Place's reply was to point out that ‘this table’ does not mean the same as ‘this old packing case’ and ‘lightning’ does not mean the same as ‘motion of electric charges. We find out whether this is a table in a different way from the way in which we find out that it is an old packing case. We find out whether a thing is a lightning by looking and that it is a motion of electric charges by theory and experiment. This does not prevent the table from being identical to the old packing case and the perceived lightning being nothing other than an electric discharge. Feigl and Smart put the matter more in terms of the distinction between meaning and reference. ‘Sensation’ and ‘brain process’ may differ in meaning and yet have the same reference. ‘Very bright planet seen in the morning’ and ‘very bright planet seen in the evening’ both refer to the same entity Venus. (Of course, these expressions?could?be construed as referring to different things, different sequences of temporal stages of Venus, but not necessarily or most naturally so.)

There did seem to be a tendency among philosophers to have thought that identity statements needed to be necessary and a priori truths. However, identity theorists have treated ‘sensations are brain processes’ as contingent. We had to?find out?what the identity holds. Aristotle, after all, thought that the brain was for cooling the blood. Descartes thought that consciousness is immaterial.

It was sometimes objected that sensation statements are incorrigible whereas statements about brains are corrigible. The inference was made that there must be something different about sensations. Ryle and in effect Wittgenstein toyed with the attractive but quite implausible notion that ostensible reports of immediate experience are not really reports but are ‘avowals. A toothache is just a sophisticated sort of wince. Place, influenced by Martin, was able to explain the relative incorrigibility of sensation statements by their low claims:’ makes a bigger claim than ‘It looks to me that there is a bent oar’. Nevertheless, my sensation and my putative awareness of the sensation are distinct existences and so, by Hume's principle, it must be possible for one to occur without the other. One should deny anything other than a relative incorrigibility as per Place.

As remarked above, Place preferred to express the theory by the notion of the constitution, whereas Smart preferred to make prominent the notion of identity as it occurs in the axioms of identity in logic. So Smart had to say that if sensation X is identical to brain process Y then if Y is between my ears and is straight or circular (absurdly to oversimplify) then sensation X is between my ears and is straight or circular. Of course, it is not presented to us as such in experience. Perhaps only the neuroscientist could know whether it is straight or circular. The professor of anatomy might be identical to the dean of the medical school. A visitor might know that the professor has hiccups in lectures but not know that the dean has hiccups in lectures.

PHENOMENAL PROPERTIES AND TOPIC-NEUTRAL ANALYSES

Someone might object that the dean of the medical school does not?qua?dean hiccup in lectures.?Qua?dean goes to meetings with the vice-chancellor. This is not to the point but there is a point behind it. This is because?the property?of being a professor of anatomy is not identical to?the property?of being the dean of the medical school. The question might be asked, that even if sensations are identical to brain processes, are there not introspected non-physical properties of sensations that are not identical with properties of brain processes? How would a physicalist identity theorist deal with this? The answer (Smart 1959) is that the properties of experiences are ‘topic neutral. Smart adapted the words ‘topic-neutral’ from Ryle, who used them to characterize words such as ‘if, ‘or’, ‘and’, ‘not’, ‘because’. If you overheard only these words in a conversation you would not be able to tell whether the conversation was one of mathematics, physics, geology, history, theology, or any other subject. Smart used the words ‘topic neutral’ in the narrower sense of being neutral between physicalism and dualism. For example, ‘going on, ‘occurring’, ‘intermittent’, ‘waxing’, and ‘waning’ is topic neutral. So is ‘me’ in so far as it refers to the utterer of the sentence in question. Thus, to say that a sensation is caused by lightning or the presence of cabbage before my eyes leave it open as to whether the sensation is non-physical as the dualist believes or physical as the materialist believes. This sentence also is neutral as to whether the properties of the sensation are physical or whether some of them are irreducibly psychical. To see how this idea can be applied to the present purpose let us consider the following example.

Suppose we have a yellow, green, and purple striped mental image. We may also introduce the philosophical term ‘sense datum’ to cover the case of seeing or seeming to see something yellow, green, and purple: we say that we have a yellow, green, and purple sense datum. That is, we would see or seem to see, for example, a flag or an array of lamps that is green, yellow, and purple striped. Suppose also, as seems plausible, that there is nothing yellow, green, and purple striped in the brain. Thus, it is important for identity theorists to say that sense data and images are not part of the furniture of the world. ‘I have a green sense datum’ is really just a way of saying that I see or seem to see something that really is green. This move should not be seen as merely an?ad hoc?device, since Ryle and J.L. Austin, in effect Wittgenstein, and others had provided arguments, as when Ryle argued that mental images were not a sort of ghostly picture postcard. Place characterized the fallacy of thinking that when we perceive something green, we are perceiving something green in the mind as ‘the phenomenological fallacy’. He characterizes this fallacy by Place the mistake of supposing that when the subject describes his experience, when he describes how things look, sound, smell, taste, or feel to him, he is describing the literal properties of objects and events on a peculiar sort of internal cinema or television screen, usually referred to in the modern psychological literature as the ‘phenomenal field’.

Of course, as Smart recognized, this leaves the identity theory dependent on a physicalist account of color. His early account of color was too behaviorist, and could not deal, for example, with the reversed spectrum problem, but he later gave a realist and objectivist account by Smart. Armstrong had been realistic about color but Smart worried that if so color would be a very idiosyncratic and disjunctive concept, of no cosmic importance, of no interest to extraterrestrials (for instance) who had different visual systems. Prompted by Lewis in conversation Smart came to realize that this was no objection to colors being objective properties.

One first gives the notion of a normal human percipient with respect to color for which there are objective tests in terms of the ability to make discriminations with respect to color. This can be done without circularity. Thus ‘discriminate with respect to color’ is a more primitive notion than that of color. (Compare the way that in set theory ‘equinumerous’ is antecedent to ‘number’.) Then Smart elucidated the notion of color in terms of discrimination with respect to the color of normal human percipients in normal conditions (say cloudy Scottish daylight). This account of color may be disjunctive and eccentric.

Maxwell's equations might be of interest to Alpha centurions but hardly our color concepts. Anthropocentric and disjunctive they may be, but objective nonetheless. David R. Hilbert identifies colors with reflectance’s, thus reducing the idiosyncrasy and disjunctive- ness. A few epicycles are easily added to deal with radiated light, the colors of rainbows or the sun at sunset, and the colors due to diffraction from feathers. John Locke was on the right track in making the secondary qualities objective as powers in the object but erred in making these powers to power to produce ideas in the mind rather than to make behavioral discriminations. Also, Smart would say that if powers are dispositions, we should treat the secondary qualities as the categorical bases of these powers, e.g., in the case of color properties of the surfaces of objects.) Locke's view suggested that the ideas have mysterious qualia observed on the screen of an internal mental theatre. However, to do Locke justice he does not talk about the effect of ‘red ideas’ but of ‘ideas of red’. Philosophers who elucidate ‘is red’ in terms of ‘looks red’ have the matter the wrong way around.

Let us return to the issue of us having a yellow, purple, and green striped sense datum or mental image, and yet there is no yellow, purple, and green striped thing in the brain. The identity theorist (Smart) can say that sense data and images are not real things in the world: they are like the average plumber. Sentences ostensibly about the average plumber can be translated into, or elucidated in terms of, sentences about plumbers. So also, there is having a green sense datum or image but not sense data or images, and the halving of a green sense datum or image is not itself green. So, it can, so far as this goes, easily be a brain process that is not green either. When we describe the after-image as green... we are saying that we are having the sort of experience which we normally have when, and which we have learned to describe as, looking at a green patch of light. And Smart ?says:

When a person says ‘I see a yellowish-orange after-image’ he is saying something like this: "There is something going on which is like what is going on when?I have my eyes open, am awake, and there is an orange illuminated in a good light in front of me".

Quoting these passages, David Chalmers (1996, p. 360) objects that if ‘something is going on is construed broadly enough it is inadequate, and if it is construed narrowly enough to cover only experiential states (or processes) it is not sufficient for the conclusion. Smart would counter this by stressing the word ‘typically’. Of course a lot of things go on in me when I have a yellow after image (for example my heart is pumping blood through my brain). However, they do not?typically?go on then: they go on at other times too. Against Place Chalmers says that the word ‘experience’ is unanalyzed and so Place's analysis is insufficient for establishing an identity between sensations and brain processes. Against Smart, he says that leaving the word ‘experience’ out of the analysis renders it inadequate. That is, he does not accept the ‘topic-neutral’ analysis. Smart hopes and Chalmers denies, that the account in terms of ‘typically of’ saves the topic-neutral analysis. In defense of Place one might perhaps say that it is not clear that the word ‘experience’ cannot be given a topic-neutral analysis, perhaps building on Farrell (1950). If we do not need the word ‘experience’ neither do we need the word ‘mental’. Rosenthal (1994) complains (against the identity theorist) that experiences have some characteristically mental properties, and that ‘We inevitably lose the distinctively mental if we construe these properties as neither physical nor mental. Of course to be topic neutral is to be able to be both physical and mental, just as arithmetic is. There is no need for the word ‘mental’ itself to occur in the topic-neutral formula. ‘Mental’, as Ryle (1949) suggests, in its ordinary use is a rather grab-bag term, ‘mental arithmetic’, ‘mental illness, etc. with which an identity theorist finds no trouble.

4. Causal Role Theories

In their accounts of mind, David Lewis and D.M. Armstrong emphasize the notion of causality. Lewis's 1966 was a particularly clear-headed presentation of the identity theory in which he says (I here refer to the reprint in Lewis 1983, p. 100):

My argument is this: The definitive characteristic of any (sort of) experience as such is its causal role, its syndrome of most typical causes and effects. But we materialists believe that these causal roles which belong by analytic necessity to experiences belong in fact to certain physical states. Since these physical states possess the definitive character of experiences, they must be experiences.

Similarly, Robert Kirk (1999) has argued for the impossibility of zombies. If the supposed zombie has all the behavioural and neural properties ascribed to it by those who argue from the possibility of zombies against materialism, then the zombie is conscious and so not a zombie.

Thus there is no need for explicit use of Ockham's Razor as in Smart (1959) though not in Place (1956). (See Place 1960.) Lewis's paper was extremely valuable and already there are hints of a marriage between the identity theory of mind and so-called ‘functionalist’ ideas that are explicit in Lewis 1972 and 1994. In his 1972 (‘Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications’) he applies ideas in his more formal paper ‘How to Define Theoretical Terms’ (1970). Folk psychology contains words such as ‘sensation’, ‘perceive’, ‘belief, ‘desire’, ‘emotion’, etc. which we recognise as psychological. Words for colours, smells, sounds, tastes and so on also occur. One can regard common sense platitudes containing both these sorts of these words as constituting a theory and we can take them as theoretical terms of common sense psychology and thus as denoting whatever entities or sorts of entities uniquely realise the theory. Then if certain neural states do so too (as we believe) then the mental states must be these neural states. In his 1994 he allows for tact in extracting a consistent theory from common sense. One cannot uncritically collect platitudes, just as in producing a grammar, implicit in our speech patterns, one must allow for departures from what on our best theory would constitute grammaticality.

A great advantage of this approach over the early identity theory is its holism. Two features of this holism should be noted. One is that the approach is able to allow for the causal interactions between brain states and processes themselves, as well as in the case of external stimuli and responses. Another is the ability to draw on the notion of Ramseyfication of a theory. F.P. Ramsey had shown how to replace the theoretical terms of a theory such as ‘the property of being an electron’ by ‘the property X such that...’. so that when this is done for all the theoretical terms, we are left only with ‘property X such that’, ‘property Y such that’ etc. Take the terms describing behaviour as the observation terms and psychological terms as the theoretical ones of folk psychology. Then Ramseyfication shows that folk psychology is compatible with materialism. This seems right, though perhaps the earlier identity theory deals more directly with reports of immediate experience.

The causal approach was also characteristic of D.M. Armstrong's careful conceptual analysis of mental states and processes, such as perception and the secondary qualities, sensation, consciousness, belief, desire, emotion, voluntary action, in his?A Materialist Theory of the Mind?(1968a) with a second edition (1993) containing a valuable new preface. Parts I and II of this book are concerned with conceptual analysis, paving the way for a contingent identification of mental states and processes with material ones. As had Brian Medlin, in an impressive critique of Ryle and defence of materialism (Medlin 1967), Armstrong preferred to describe the identity theory as ‘Central State Materialism’. Independently of Armstrong and Lewis, Medlin's central state materialism depended, as theirs did, on a causal analysis of concepts of mental states and processes. See Medlin 1967, and 1969 (including endnote 1).

Mention should particularly be made here of two of Armstrong's other books, one on perception (1961), and one on bodily sensations, (1962). Armstrong thought of perception as?coming to believe by means of the senses?(compare also Pitcher 1971). This combines the advantages of Direct Realism with hospitality towards the scientific causal story which had been thought to have supported the earlier representative theory of perception. Armstrong regarded bodily sensations as perceptions of states of our body. Of course the latter may be mixed up with emotional states, as an itch may include a propensity to scratch, and contrariwise in exceptional circumstances pain may be felt without distress. However, Armstrong sees the central notion here as that of perception. This suggests a terminological problem. Smart had talked of visual sensations. These were not perceptions but something which occurred in perception. So in?this?sense of ‘sensation’ there should be bodily sensation sensations. The ambiguity could perhaps be resolved by using the word ‘sensing’ in the context of ‘visual’, ‘auditory’, ‘tactile’ and ‘bodily’, so that bodily sensations would be perceivings which involved introspectible ‘sensings’. These bodily sensations are perceptions and there can be misperceptions as when a person with his foot amputated can think that he has a pain in the foot. He has a sensing ‘having a pain in the foot’ but the world does not contain a pain in the foot, just as it does not contain sense data or images but does contain havings of sense data and of images.

Armstrong's central state materialism involved identifying beliefs and desires with states of the brain (1968a). Smart came to agree with this. On the other hand Place resisted the proposal to extend the identity theory to dispositional states such as beliefs and desires. He stressed that we do not have privileged access to our beliefs and desires. Like Ryle he thought of beliefs and desires as to be elucidated by means of hypothetical statements about behaviour and gave the analogy of the horsepower of a car (Place 1967). However he held that the dispute here is not so much about the neural basis of mental states as about the nature of dispositions. His views on dispositions are argued at length in his debate with Armstrong and Martin (Armstrong, Martin and Place, T. Crane (ed.) 1996). Perhaps we can be relaxed about whether mental states such as beliefs and desires are dispositions or are topic neutrally described neurophysiological states and return to what seems to be the more difficult issue of consciousness. Causal identity theories are closely related to Functionalism, to be discussed in the next section. Smart had been wary of the notion of causality in metaphysics believing that it had no place in theoretical physics. However even so he should have admitted it in folk psychology and also in scientific psychology and biology generally, in which physics and chemistry are applied to explain generalisations rather than strict laws. If folk psychology uses the notion of causality, it is no matter if it is what Quine has called second grade discourse, involving the very contextual notions of modality.

5. Functionalism and Identity Theory

It has commonly been thought that the identity theory has been superseded by a theory called ‘functionalism’. It could be argued that functionalists greatly exaggerate their difference from identity theorists. Indeed some philosophers, such as Lewis (1972 and 1994) and Jackson, Pargetter and Prior (1982), have seen functionalism as a route towards an identity theory.

Like Lewis and Armstrong, functionalists define mental states and processes in terms of their causal relations to behaviour but stop short of identifying them with their neural realisations. Of course the term ‘functionalism’ has been used vaguely and in different ways, and it could be argued that even the theories of Place, Smart and Armstrong were at bottom functionalist. The word ‘functionalist’ has affinities with that of ‘function’ in mathematics and also with that of ‘function’ in biology. In mathematics a function is a set of ordered n-tuples. Similarly if mental processes are defined directly or indirectly by sets of stimulus-response pairs the definitions could be seen as ‘functional’ in the mathematical sense. However there is probably a closer connection with the term as it is used in biology, as one might define ‘eye’ by its function even though a fly's eye and a dog's eye are anatomically and physiologically very different. Functionalism identifies mental states and processes by means of their causal roles, and as noted above in connection with Lewis, we know that the functional roles are possessed by neural states and processes. (There are teleological and homuncular forms of functionalism, which I do not consider here.) Nevertheless an interactionist dualist such as the eminent neurophysiologist Sir John Eccles would (implausibly for most of us) deny that all functional roles are so possessed. One might think of folk psychology, and indeed much of cognitive science too, as analogous to a ‘block diagram’ in electronics. A box in the diagram might be labelled (say) ‘intermediate frequency amplifier’ while remaining) neutral as to the exact circuit and whether the amplification is carried out by a thermionic valve or by a transistor. Using terminology of F. Jackson and P. Pettit (1988, pp. 381–400) the ‘role state’ would be given by ‘amplifier’, the ‘realiser state’ would be given by ‘thermionic valve’, say. So we can think of functionalism as a ‘black box’ theory. This line of thought will be pursued in the next section.

Thinking very much in causal terms about beliefs and desires fits in very well not only with folk psychology but also with Humean ideas about the motives of action. Though this point of view has been criticised by some philosophers it does seem to be right, as can be seen if we consider a possible robot aeroplane designed to find its way from Melbourne to Sydney. The designer would have to include an electronic version of something like a map of south-eastern Australia. This would provide the ‘belief’ side. One would also have to program in an electronic equivalent of ‘go to Sydney’. This program would provide the ‘desire’ side. If wind and weather pushed the aeroplane off course then negative feedback would push the aeroplane back on to the right course for Sydney. The existence of purposive mechanisms has at last (I hope) shown to philosophers that there is nothing mysterious about teleology. Nor are there any great semantic problems over intentionality (with a ‘t’). Consider the sentence ‘Joe desires a unicorn’. This is not like ‘Joe kicks a football’. For Joe to kick a football there must be a football to be kicked, but there are no unicorns. However we can say ‘Joe desires-true of himself "possesses a unicorn" ’. Or more generally ‘Joe believes-true S’ or ‘Joe desires-true S’ where S is an appropriate sentence (Quine 1960, pp. 206–16). Of course if one does not want to relativise to a language one needs to insert ‘or some samesayer of S’ or use the word ‘proposition’, and this involves the notion of proposition or intertranslatability. Even if one does not accept Quine's notion of indeterminacy of translation, there is still fuzziness in the notions of ‘belief’ and ‘desire’ arising from the fuzziness of ‘analyticity’ and ‘synonymy’. The identity theorist could say that on any occasion this fuzziness is matched by the fuzziness of the brain state that constitutes the belief or desire. Just how many interconnections are involved in a belief or desire? On a holistic account such as Lewis's one need not suppose that individuation of beliefs and desires is precise, even though good enough for folk psychology and Humean metaethics. Thus the way in which the brain represents the world might not be like a language. The representation might be like a map. A map relates every feature on it to every other feature. Nevertheless maps contain a finite amount of information. They have not infinitely many parts, still less continuum many. We can think of beliefs as expressing the different bits of information that could be extracted from the map. Thinking in this way beliefs would correspond near enough to the individualist beliefs characteristic of folk and Humean psychology.

6. Type and Token Identity Theories

The notion ‘type’ and ‘token’ here comes by analogy from ‘type’ and ‘token’ as applied to words. A telegram ‘love and love and love’ contains only two type words but in another sense, as the telegraph clerk would insist, it contains five words (‘token words’). Similarly a particular pain (more exactly a having a pain) according to the token identity theory is identical to a particular brain process. A functionalist could agree to this. Functionalism came to be seen as an improvement on the identity theory, and as inconsistent with it, because of the correct assertion that a functional state can be realised by quite different brain states: thus a functional state might be realised by a silicon based brain as well as by a carbon based brain, and leaving robotics or science fiction aside, my feeling of toothache could be realised by a different neural process from what realises your toothache.

As far as this goes a functionalist can at any rate accept token identities. Functionalists commonly deny type identities. However Jackson, Pargetter and Prior (1982) and Braddon-Mitchell and Jackson (1996) argue that this is an over-reaction on the part of the functionalist. (Indeed they see functionalism as a route to the identity theory.) The functionalist may define mental states as having some state or other (e.g., carbon based or silicon based) which accounts for the functional properties. The functionalist second order state is a state of having some first order state or other which causes or is caused by the behaviour to which the functionalist alludes. In this way we have a second order type theory. Compare brittleness. The brittleness of glass and the brittleness of biscuits are both the state of having some property which explains their breaking, though the first order physical property may be different in the two cases. This way of looking at the matter is perhaps more plausible in relation to mental states such as beliefs and desires than it is to immediately reported experiences. When I report a toothache I do seem to be concerned with first order properties, even though topic neutral ones.

If we continue to concern ourselves with first order properties, we could say that the type-token distinction is not an all or nothing affair. We could say that human experiences are brain processes of one lot of sorts and Alpha Centaurian experiences are brain processes of another lot of sorts. We could indeed propose much finer classifications without going to the limit of mere token identities.

How restricted should be the restriction of a restricted type theory? How many hairs must a bald man have no more of? An identity theorist would expect his toothache today to be very similar to his toothache yesterday. He would expect his toothache to be quite similar to his wife's toothache. He would expect his toothache to be somewhat similar to his cat's toothache. He would not be confident about similarity to an extra-terrestrial's pain. Even here, however, he might expect some similarities of wave form or the like.

Even in the case of the similarity of my pain now to my pain ten minutes ago, there will be unimportant dissimilarities, and also between my pain and your pain. Compare topiary, making use of an analogy exploited by Quine in a different connection. In English country gardens the tops of box hedges are often cut in various shapes, for example peacock shapes. One might make generalizations about peacock shapes on box hedges, and one might say that all the imitation peacocks on a particular hedge have the same shape. However if we approach the two imitation peacocks and peer into them to note the precise shapes of the twigs that make them up we will find differences. Whether we say that two things are similar or not is a matter of abstractness of description. If we were to go to the limit of concreteness the types would shrink to single membered types, but there would still be no ontological difference between identity theory and functionalism.

An interesting form of token identity theory is the anomalous monism of Davidson 1980. Davidson argues that causal relations occur under the neural descriptions but not under the descriptions of psychological language. The latter descriptions use intentional predicates, but because of indeterminacy of translation and of interpretation, these predicates do not occur in law statements. It follows that mind-brain identities can occur only on the level of individual (token) events. It would be beyond the scope of the present essay to consider Davidson's ingenious approach, since it differs importantly from the more usual forms of identity theory.

7. Consciousness

Place answered the question ‘Is Consciousness a Brain Process?’ in the affirmative. But what sort of brain process? It is natural to feel that there is something ineffable about which no mere neurophysiological process (with only physical intrinsic properties) could have. There is a challenge to the identity theorist to dispel this feeling.

Suppose that I am riding my bicycle from my home to the university. Suddenly I realize that I have crossed a bridge over a creek, gone along a twisty path for half a mile, avoided oncoming traffic, and so on, and yet have no memories.?Still, it probably does happen, and if it does the driver is conscious only in the sense that he or she is alert to the route, of oncoming traffic etc., i.e., is perceiving in the sense of ‘coming to believe by means of the senses. The driver gets the beliefs but is not aware of doing so. There is no suggestion of ineffability in this sense of ‘consciousness’, for which I shall reserve the term ‘awareness’.

For the full consciousness, the one that puzzles us and suggests ineffability, we need the sense elucidated by Armstrong in a debate with Norman Malcolm.

In the debate with Norman Malcolm, Armstrong compared consciousness with proprioception. A case of proprioception occurs when with our eyes shut and without touch, we are immediately aware of the angle at which one of our elbows is bent. That is, proprioception is a special sense, different from that of bodily sensation, in which we become aware of parts of our body. Now the brain is part of our body and so perhaps immediate awareness of a process in, or a state of, our brain may here for present purposes be called ‘proprioception’. Thus, the proprioception even though the neuroanatomy is different. Thus the proprioception which constitutes consciousness, as distinguished from mere awareness, is a higher order awareness, a perception of one part of (or configuration in) our brain by the brain itself. Some may sense circularity here. If so let them suppose that the proprioception occurs in practice negligible time after the process proprioceptor. Then perhaps there can be proprioception’s.s, and so on up, though in fact, the sequence will probably not go up more than two or three steps. The last proprioception in the sequence will not be proprioception, and this may help to explain our sense of the ineffability of consciousness. Compare Gilbert Ryle in?The Concept of Mind?on the systematic elusiveness of ‘I’

Place has argued that the function of the ‘automatic pilot, to which he refers as ‘the zombie within’, is to alert consciousness to inputs that it identifies as problematic, while it ignores non-problematic inputs or re-routes them to output without the need for conscious awareness. For this view of consciousness see Place.

Later Objections to the Identity Theory

Mention should here be made of influential criticisms of the identity theory by Saul Kripke and David Chalmers respectively. It will not be possible to discuss them in great detail, partly because of the fact that Kripke's remarks rely on views about modality, possible worlds semantics, and essentialism which some philosophers would want to contest, and because Chalmers' long and rich book would deserve a lengthy answer. Kripke (1980) calls an expression a rigid designator if it refers to the same object in every possible world. Or in counterpart theory it would have an exactly similar counterpart in every possible world. It seems to me that what we count as counterparts is highly contextual. Take the example ‘water is H2O’. In another world, or in a twin earth in our world as Putnam imagines (1975), the stuff found in rivers, lakes, the sea would not be H2O but XYZ and so would not be water. This is certainly giving preference to real chemistry over folk chemistry, and so far I applaud this. There are therefore contexts in which we say that on twin earth or the envisaged possible world the stuff found in rivers would not be water. Nevertheless there are contexts in which we could envisage a possible world (write a science fiction novel) in which being found in rivers and lakes and the sea, assuaging thirst and sustaining life was more important than the chemical composition and so XYZ would be the counterpart of H2O.

Kripke considers the identity ‘heat = molecular motion’, and holds that this is true in every possible world and so is a necessary truth. Actually, the proposition is not quite true, for what about radiant heat? What about heat as defined in classical thermodynamics which is ‘topic neutral’ compared with statistical thermodynamics? Still, suppose that heat has an essence and that it is molecular motion, or at least is in the context envisaged. Kripke says ?that when we think that molecular motion might exist in the absence of heat we are confusing this with thinking that the molecular motion might have existed without being?felt?as heat. He asks whether it is analogously possible that if pain is a certain sort of brain process that it has existed without being?felt?as pain. He suggests that the answer is ‘No’. An identity theorist who accepted the account of consciousness as a higher order perception could answer ‘Yes’. We might be aware of a damaged tooth and also of being in an agitation condition (to use Ryle's term for emotional states) without being aware of our awareness. An identity theorist such as Smart would prefer talk of ‘having a pain’ rather than of ‘pain’: pain is not part of the furniture of the world any more than a sense datum or the average plumber is. Kripke concludes that the apparent contingency of the connection between the mental state and the corresponding brain state thus cannot be explained by some sort of qualitative analogue as in the case of heat. Smart would say that there is a sense in which the connection of sensations (sensing’s) and brain processes is only half contingent. A complete description of the brain state or process (including causes and effects of it) would imply the report of inner experience, but the latter, being topic neutral and so very abstract would not imply the neurological description.

Chalmers in the course of his exhaustive study of consciousness developed a theory of non-physical qualia which to some extent avoids the worry about nomological danglers. The worry expressed by Smart (1959) is that if there were non-physical qualia there would, most implausibly, have to be laws relating neurophysiological processes to apparently simple properties, and the correlation laws would have to be fundamental, mere danglers from the nomological net (as Feigl called it) of science. Chalmers counters this by supposing that the qualia are not simple but unknown to us, are made up of simple proto-qualia, and that the fundamental laws relating these to physical entities relate them to?fundamental?physical entities. His view comes to a rather interesting panpsychism. On the other hand, if the topic neutral account is correct, then qualia are no more than points in a multidimensional similarity space, and the overwhelming plausibility will fall on the side of the identity theorist.

On Chalmers' view how are we aware of non-physical qualia? It has been suggested above that this inner awareness is proprioception of the brain by the brain. But what sort of story is possible in the case of awareness of a quale? Chalmers could have some sort of answer to this by means of his principle of coherence according to which the causal neurological story parallels the story of succession of qualia. It is not clear however that this would make us aware of the qualia. The qualia do not seem to be needed in the physiological story of how an antelope avoids a tiger.

People often think that even if a robot could scan its own perceptual processes this would not mean that the robot was conscious. This appeals to our intuitions, but perhaps we could reverse the argument and say that because the robot can be aware of its awareness the robot?is?conscious. I have given reason above to distrust intuitions, but in any case, Chalmers comes some of the ways in that he toys with the idea that a thermostat has a sort of proto-qualia. The dispute between identity theorists (and physicalists generally) and Chalmers comes down to our attitude to phenomenology. Certainly, walking in a forest, seeing the blue of the sky, the green of the trees, and the red of the track, one may find it hard to believe that our qualia are merely points in multidimensional similarity space. But perhaps that is what?it is like?(to use a phrase that can be distrusted) to be aware of a point in multidimensional similarity space. One may also, as Place would suggest, be subject to ‘the phenomenological fallacy’. At the end of his book, Chalmers makes some speculations about the interpretation of quantum mechanics. If they succeed then perhaps, we could envisage Chalmers' theory as integrated into physics and him as a physicalist after all. However, it could be doubted whether we need to go down to the quantum level to understand consciousness or hideousness.

Conclusion

There are just ample efforts but stills we do get not any signification. ?Let us keep us our search to unravel full facts

要查看或添加评论,请登录

社区洞察

其他会员也浏览了