On the philosophy of systems
Preface
This article is a postcript to five other articles you should read the first. This a collection of notes that didn't make the cut in the earlier articles!
Philosophers today devote much time to rejecting or endorsing earlier philosophers, and positioning themselves in relation to them. They like to review, interpret and put a new spin each other's ideas, using language that is often impenetrable to outsiders.
To read the articles above you need next to no knowledge of philosophy, linguistics or mathematics. In fact. thinking in terms of traditional "isms" and "ologies" may hinder you from reading them right. To associate our philosophy of systems with one particular philosopher or school would bring a lot of baggage into the picture, endless room for debate, and cloud the story.
Having said, this article was written for readers interested in the relationship of philosopical positions to systems thinking. First, let me mention an approach deprecated here.
Constructivism - dismissed
Western governments and institutions are being captured by ideologies that are, in effect, substituting opinion for science.
Relativism is the doctrine that there is no absolute or verifiable truth, because knowledge emerges separately in each culture or society. Social constructionism is a radical form of relativism that denies the things studied by scientists are “out there”. Rather, it says things are entirely constructed through ways of observing and describing the world that are specific to each social context.
This philosophy leads some to conclude that opinions are as valid as evidence. Some sociologists have latched on to this philosophy as a rationale for not applying the scientific method, and found a way of talking ("my truth") that hides the underpinning philosophy.
Some interpret "my truth" as meaning that, since a receiver's interpretation of a message is true, then if a receiver is offended by the message, it is the fault of the sender. This is extraordinarily unjust. If a message receiver takes offence, the sender is blamed, however innocent they are or kindly they meant the message.
If someone misreads your message "Don't go near the cliff edge", should you be blamed when they fall down the cliff? If somebody on Tik Tok says "I read your post to be racist", does that prove you are a racist?
On description and reality
In a post-Newton, post-Darwin, post-Einstein world, scientists don't claim to understand reality directly or completely. They observe and envisage reality as being composed of interrelated things. They describe and typify those things in models that they judge to be true in so far as they help to predict what happens. They don't claim to understand reality beyond the models they make of it.
All models are partial; many are imperfect. We test and refine models by trial and error. Biological evolution has rewarded animals better able to model reality biochemically. And science has progressed by envisaging and constructing models, using them to make predictions, then observing and testing how well phenomena match those predictions.
Axiomatically: there is a reality out there (the alternative is useless sophistry), the descriptions we make of reality are also real, our descriptions may be verified empirically. All we can know of reality is what we can describe of it in models (in memories and in messages) that are true to the extent that they help us detect and predict what happens.
A reader has suggested this position close to critical realism. But classifying that wasy may obscure more than it clarifies; not least because there are many sub-schools, some overlapping.
Earlier articles advanced several more particular propositions about description and reality.
After A J Ayer: "To describe a thing is to classify it".
After Humberto Maturana: "Knowledge is a biological phenomenon".
In short, we create and use types to describe things. A philosophy of systems must address how we create and use abstract system models to represent real systems.
Empiricism
This work takes a pragmatic empirical approach.
Science (and all reasoned argument of the kind that should inform government decisions) presumes not only that things do exist out there in the world, but we can observe features of those things, and describe them.
Social constructivists dismiss empiricism based on a false argument. They say empiricists cannot prove assertions. But empiricists don't presume that proof is possible or necessary.
I take a psycho-biological view of these things. Every animal with a brain lives its life as a pragmatic empiricist. How the brain works is irrelevant. All that matters is its evident ability to predict the future well enough to make decisions about actions, such as to stop before walking over a cliff edge.
领英推荐
On other "isms" and "ologies"
Empiricism is not enough, since not all knowledge is acquired by empirical testing of evidence against theories or models.
Logical positivism is not enough, since not all problems can be solved by logical analysis. (Having said that, testing and logical analysis are the primary ways to verify a model.)
Anthropomorphism is misleading, partly because it leads philosophers down a linguistics dead end.
Constructivist ontology, the idea that reality is socially constructed through language, is too anthropocentric. Evidently, non-social animals can remember things they have observed in reality, and interact with them. True, the human ability to make and share models was vastly increased by the evolution of verbal language. But to survive, every sentient being models things in its environment.
Moreover, the following psycho-biological view of thinking spans most if not all of the headings below
Putting aside the "isms" and "ologies" above, the approach taken in these articles is to take a psycho-biological and Darwinian view of how thinking evolved, in accord with
Reductionism
Some speak of "system engineering" in a dismissive way by calling it systematic rather than systemic, reductionistic rather than holistic, analytic rather than synthetic.
Deprecating reductionism is naive. To begin with, the term is ambiguous. For some, it means reducing every explanation of things to the level of physics. Clearly, scientists do not do this. In higher level sciences, higher level phenomena are explained without reference to physics, and other lower level sciences.
Others reject reductionism in favor of holism; yet they are inseparable sides of one coin. You cannot join up parts without first identifying the parts of interest, which is in effect to bound the whole composite of interest and decompose it as you see fit.
All scientific thinking involves both zooming in and zooming out as far as befits understanding or explaining the phenomena of interest. Zoom out far enough, to consider the cosmology of the universe, and you return to the domain of physics, in which the trials and tribulations of human kind are irrelevant.
Moreover, the mereologist's view that things are well explained in terms of wholes and parts is also naive, since one person's whole is another person's part, and systems thinking is more about the effects of interactions between things than the things themselves.
Further reading
This is one of several related articles that how show the ideas of famous systems thinkers (Ashby, Forrester, Ackoff, Meadows, Beer, Senge and others) can be embraced in a coherent system theory, provided you recognise that not everything is well-called a system, and not every approach to thinking about a social entity is well-called systems thinking.
Aside: Boulding on the limits of system theory
Boulding 1956 suggested a possible arrangement of system levels, rising (he said) in complexity.
Boulding suggested that higher-level systems are larger and/or more complex than lower-level systems. So social entities are larger and more complex than plants. However, the interactions between the many cells of a plant (level 5) may be more complex than the interactions between a few animals in a simple social organization (level 8).
In 1968, Bertalanffy wrote Boulding’s hierarchy was “impressionistic and intuitive with no claim for logical rigor”. However, some ideas below foreshadow the ones in this book.
In other words, a real-world entity at levels 5 to 9 cannot be modeled as a system. We can only model particular ways of behaving as systems.
In other words, actors' behavior in a real system in action is defined as roles in an abstract system.
Auto-catalyst, facilitating our common future. Author of Faciliteren als Tweede Beroep, co-author of Body of Practice. Founder of mind@work VOF
2 年I’ve been thinking about thinking too. I’ve usually used the word “system” for human made systems or machines only. Only when one can reassemble parts and get a functioning ‘whole’ I tend to use the word system. One cannot know “how” one thinks. To paraphrase Paul Watzlawick: all thinking is behaving and all behaving is thinking. One cannot not think. Thinking happens to be pragmatic. There’s no thinking without a body and any-body (or should I say every-body) “thinks”. If it behaves like a thinker it thinks. This thinking consists of constructing “metaphors”, what you might call “models”. These models model one’s body and one’s behaviour and one uses these metaphors to predict future behaviour of one’s body <--> thinking. That’s why I call these “metaphor-in-use”. Using one’s body improves one thinking. Usually. The thinking brain - the way it behaves - is structurally coupled with the way one’s behaving body behaves and the body behaves structurally coupled with its domains (I prefer domain, as domains become also structurally coupled to bodies). Given enough time, Shannon proved, any codeing or modelling will become an error-correcting code or model.
Retired
2 年Graham Berrisford Hi Graham, I’v e been thinking about your claims about descriptions and types i.e. every description is a type and every type is a description. I think you need to examine closely what?you mean by a ‘type’ and by a ’description’ since these ideas seem very close to this that get you to Russell’s paradox. The paradox is usually constructed in naive set theory but can be constructed in naive type theories.Given a type, say T, we can ask if something, say x, is of that type e.g. x is_a T. Since types and descriptions are co-extensive then T can be given by a description. So we construct the description ’the type T of all types t such that not (t is_a t )’. We then ask is T of type T i.e. T is_a T. If T is_a T then we have a contradiction, but is not( T is_a T) we also have a contradiction.
40yrs (Data) Systems Analysis & Design + Neu-Net simulations of the Pros & Cons of our Fast; path-dependent, (stochastic abductive) & Slow; (rule following 'truth' directed) Thinking = Schema/Map Assembly & Navigation
2 年Description is a 1-to-1 use of 'is' - x is green Type can be (is usually reserved for) a 1-to-many use of 'is one of many members of ' x is one of many members of the type green. so not the same and why not 'things in relationships' in you phenomenon box?
Seeker of better questions
2 年Understanding evolves from analysis AND synthesis!
Seeker of better questions
2 年Thinkers observe phenomena that they represent with models as a basis for evolving their thinking.